The USPTO and the USCO Must Resolve Their Disparate Approaches to AI Inventorship and Copyrightability

“Before advising the President, the USPTO and USCO should not adopt contradictory approaches to AI’s contribution to the world of innovation and the useful arts.”

AIThe President’s recent Executive Order on the Safe, Secure, and Trustworthy Development and Use of Artificial Intelligence instructs the U.S. Patent and Trademark Office (USPTO) Director and Copyright Registrar to collaboratively issue recommendations to the President on further actions for advancing AI innovation through intellectual property, particularly with respect to AI inventorship and AI authorship. But the two offices currently regard AI differently in terms of assessing the creative and conceiving capabilities of machines, which poses a potential contradiction in how intellectual property law treats AI.

On the issue of AI inventorship, the question rests on whether AI contributed to the conception of an invention. The essence of the USPTO’s and the Federal Circuit’s decisions in Thaler v. Vidal is that conception is not presumed. As it stands, the USPTO definitely does not see machines as being capable of conception. However, the U.S. Copyright Office’s (USCO’s) position on AI authorship seemingly conflicts with the USPTO’s position, as the USCO adopts a de minimis test that automatically precludes copyrightability to any portion of work in which the AI’s contribution is determined to be more than de minimis.

Thus, the USCO’s de minimis test actually presumes creativity by the AI and fundamentally contradicts with the USPTO’s assessment of AI inventorship, which sees that AI is not capable of conception. If AI is not capable of conceiving by the USPTO, why is AI automatically presumed to be creative by the USCO? Similarly, if AI is capable of being creative before the USCO, then why is AI regarded as not capable of conceiving by the USPTO? How can the USCO’s de minimis test for precluding copyrightability exist concurrently with the USPTO’s position that AI is not capable of conceiving an invention? Before advising the President, the USPTO and USCO should not adopt contradictory approaches to AI’s contribution to the world of innovation and the useful arts.

The USPTO Does not Presume AI is Capable of Conception

The majority view by patent practitioners is that AI is not capable of conception that is “the formation in the mind of the inventor, of a definite and permanent idea of the complete and operative invention, as it is hereafter to be applied in practice.” Burroughs Wellcome Co. v. Barr Labs., Inc., 40 F.3d 1223, 1228 (Fed. Cir. 1994).

For example, in Corey Salsberg’s testimony to the Senate Judiciary Committee on AI inventorship, he noted that, despite generating 282 novel candidate molecules by Novartis’s AI-enabled research platform, JAEGER, only two were identified to have potential for further drug development. “JAEGER neither identified a problem, nor considered how to address it without prompting from human scientists and modeling from human-made precedents. Nor did it appreciate the properties or utility of its outputs, which had to be further analyzed, synthesized, developed and tested by humans before the results were realized,” Salsberg testified.

In the case of DABUS, the USPTO did not even examine Dr. Thaler’s invention, as his application was deemed incomplete for failing to list an inventor as a machine and was automatically determined to be incapable of conceiving under the current laws. Generative AI in its current form is widely regarded to be incapable of recognition and appreciation of the invention, which is required for inventorship.

The De Minimis Test Adopted by the Copyright Guidance Presumes AI Creativity

Under the USCO’s current rules, AI-generated content that is more than de minimis must be disclaimed. The USCO’s AI Guidance cites Feist v. Rural Telephone, which established the de minimis test for human authorship. “As a constitutional matter,” the Feist Court noted, “copyright protects only those constituent elements of a work that possess more than a de minimis quantum of creativity.”

The Guidance adopts the de minimis standard, citing Feist, as if this test as applied to AI authorship is based on historical precedent. However, the de minimis test adopted in Feist was applied as a standard for a finding of copyrightability while the de minimis standard now used for AI is a standard for precluding copyrightability.

In applying the test, the USCO makes a determination on whether the work would have been copyrightable had it been executed by a human. If yes, then copyrightability is precluded because the Copyright Act only permits human ownership of copyrights. But by viewing AI’s work as if it were created by a human, the USCO essentially assumes that the AI is being creative.

Take the case of Joseph Allen’s work in “Théâtre D’opéra Spatial”.  Here, the Board found that the artistic work contains more than a de minimis amount of content generated by AI and this content must therefore be disclaimed in an application for registration. Allen’s creativity clearly also met the de minimis standard, yet the AI-generated portion must be disclaimed. Artistic images created by integrating both AI and human input like Allen’s suffers under this test because having to disclaim the AI’s contribution so diminishes the work such that whatever remaining portion subsequently copyrighted fails to cover the artistic value of the integrated piece.

Historically, creativity was found based on finding of a work’s originality. The Copyright Act protects “original works of authorship fixed in any tangible medium of expression, now known or later developed, from which they can be perceived, reproduced, or otherwise communicated, either directly or with the aid of a machine or device.” 17 U.S.C. § 102(a). Copyright law only protects “the fruits of intellectual labor” that “are founded in the creative powers of the mind.” Trade-Mark Cases, 100 U.S. 82, 94 (1879). Associating creativity with originality makes sense when it comes to the human mind – one can reasonably assume that original works were birthed in the creative powers of the human mind.

But should that same assumption really be applied in the case of AI-generated works? Just because AI generated an original work, should the AI be deemed to be creative? If that is the case, then the corollary test in patent inventorship should allow for patentability of novel outputs generated by machines such as DABUS and JAEGER and view these machines as capable of conceiving. Or instead, should both patent law and copyright law consistently see AI as simply executing a series of computer implemented steps based on an algorithm?

The Issue of AI authorship arguably requires a much more nuanced approach when it comes to different levels of AI contribution in literary and visual works, which is a difficult matter. Copyright protection obviously should not extend to works generated solely by AI. But the current law already accounts for this situation by precluding copyrightability in the cases in which there is no human author. The difficult cases are the ones like “Théâtre D’opéra Spatial” and “Zarya of the Dawn” created from both significant human and AI input. Rather than adopt a split-the-baby approach under the de minimis test, which requires disclaiming AI contribution, the USCO should consider adopting a “substantial contribution test” to assess the degree of human input and allow for copyright protection to extend to the entirety of the work when met.

Image Source: Deposit Photos
Author: yacobchuk1
Image ID: 162843412 

Share

Warning & Disclaimer: The pages, articles and comments on IPWatchdog.com do not constitute legal advice, nor do they create any attorney-client relationship. The articles published express the personal opinion and views of the author as of the time of publication and should not be attributed to the author’s employer, clients or the sponsors of IPWatchdog.com.

Join the Discussion

8 comments so far.

  • [Avatar for Anon]
    Anon
    November 20, 2023 10:40 am

    Jerry is correct (and this points to a — perhaps ‘technical’ distinction in that Congress acted to imbue an actual non-human creator with a status of “author”).

    While this additional word has never been challenged in Courts as perhaps exceeding the Constitutional grant of authority to Congress, the Supreme Court has indicated that THAT Constitutional enabling phrase IS LIMITED TO real humans as being original creators in the use of that singular grant of authority in the patent sense (See Roche v. Stanford).

    Also, I had thought that I had previously posted a warning not to follow Walter Tau’s first comment below, but I do not see it in the comment string (I may well have not posted it). The warning: listing oneself as inventor when that person knows that he is not in fact the legal inventor (as would be the case of a person merely opening a black box into which an invention has been placed) is fraud on the Office and will destroy any obtained patent. This is different than merely “oops, not listing the correct inventor” which can be fixed. As such, the advice of the first comment is most definitely NOT advice to be followed.

  • [Avatar for Jerry]
    Jerry
    November 18, 2023 12:57 pm

    “the Copyright Act only permits human ownership of copyrights.” This is not correct. Any entity can own copyrights.

    Nor would it be correct to say, as some do, that the Copyright Act only permits human “authors”. Corporations can be “authors” under the Copyright Act’s work-made-for-hire provisions.

  • [Avatar for Anon]
    Anon
    November 13, 2023 10:11 am

    Also, the USCO line of thought – presaged by the Simian Selfie case (as I have presented) – does not hide from the fact that some THING was there. That case simply – and logically – dealt with the fact by noting the Lockian nature of the patent clause and that ANY inchoate right that is to be made into a full set (basket) of property rights MUST have its origins in human creation. Simian creation – like AI creation – does not count at the onset.

    THIS is a simple – and direct – application and understanding of the fundamentals of Article I Section 8 Clause 8.

  • [Avatar for Anon]
    Anon
    November 13, 2023 10:07 am

    … it is improper to rely on DICTA from Burroughs for the legal definition of “‘inventor.”

    See also, my prior ‘thought experiments” of a person in a second room being presented with the invention — by another — in a black box that has been brought into that second room.

    Like it or not, with generative AI (and as will be more and more evident, as the versions roll out), non-human creation is a real thing.

    We would be much better off admitting such and then turn around and wrestling with HOW we should treat legal concepts such as co-inventorship and what that other legal fiction (not real person) known as Person Having Ordinary Skill In The Art treats State of the Art in the realm of obviousness – 35 USC 103 rather then desparately try to hold onto the view that non-human invention (creation) exists.

  • [Avatar for Anon]
    Anon
    November 13, 2023 10:00 am

    This statement is in clear error: “As it stands, the USPTO definitely does not see machines as being capable of conception.

  • [Avatar for TFCFM]
    TFCFM
    November 13, 2023 09:49 am

    >>> the USCO adopts a de minimis test that automatically precludes copyrightability to any portion of work in which the AI’s contribution is determined to be more than de minimis.

    Thus, the USCO’s de minimis test actually presumes creativity by the AI …<<<

    This seems to me less like "presumes creativity" and more like "presumes NON-creativity DESPITE the facial appearance of creativity."

    I can toss a box of "refrigerator magnet poetry" pieces at my refrigerator and submit the resulting jumble for registration. My box of magnets has not exhibited "creativity," despite the facial appearance thereof.

    Ditto if I tossed the magnets through some sort of a magnetic filter that placed noun magnets, verb magnets, adjective magnets, and adverb magnets into roughly-grammatically-correct positions on my refrigerator door.

  • [Avatar for Michael]
    Michael
    November 13, 2023 07:10 am

    The ChatGPT type AI can create words and images. These words and images can be used to describe an invention, but AI cannot create an invention, only the words and images used to describe it. The patent application is not the invention just the legal document used to create it. However, in copyright space, the work of art is the words and images, and AI can create the exact object for which copyright protection is sought.

  • [Avatar for Walter Tau]
    Walter Tau
    November 12, 2023 03:50 pm

    I do not see any problems with applying different standards to patent inventorship and copyright authorship. After all, copyrightability does not include the criterion of “non-obviousness” like patentability does. Any garbage generated by AI would pass the copyrightability tests as long as it is “novel”. To prevent large amounts of such garbage from overtaken the copyrighted space, AI authorship should be denied in the purposivist interpretation of the US Constitution.
    On the other hand, as the author admits, patents undergo examination (at least in the USA) and face a higher scrutinity before issuance, than AI can currently pass. Furthermore, patentability is “negated by the manner in which the invention was made.” (https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Flash_of_genius) A human can legally use AI to make an invention, and then file a patent application listing herself as a single inventor.